Visual argumentation in the Hungarian Competition Authority's
proceedings1
Introduction
Advertisements are a shared subject
of inquiry for media theory and
argumentation the-ory. Commercial interests provide a prime field for
observing innovative persuasion techniques. Marketers utilize verbal
tools and visuality; these tools are usually analyzed in rhetorical
terms and with good reason, for the persuasive power of advertisements
is mainly rhetorical. Moreover, one might even go on to say that this
is the only the kind of analysis available, since we cannot express
arguments by visual means. However, informal logicians have claimed
that visual arguments are not only possible but actually exist and can
be analyzed and evaluated in roughly the same way as verbal arguments.
In this paper we will argue that they are right. In particular, we will
explore in some detail how visual arguments can be reconstructed and
point out the similarities to and the differences from the
reconstruction of verbal arguments. We will then substantiate these
claims by providing a complete reconstruction of the visual (strictly
speaking, multi¬modal) argument given by Unilever for the superiority
of its product, Dove Intensive Cream, in a famous and
controversial
2
commercial
involving the “tulip test”.
We will start with a brief description of the informal logic tradition
and explain how it makes room for visual arguments. Then, relying on
this understanding of visual arguments, we are going to explain what
steps the reconstruction of visual arguments involves. Finally, we will
use the Dove commercial to demonstrate how these steps look like in
practice.
The Informal Logic Tradition
In the late 1970s a group of
philosophers started to develop
“non-formal standards, procedures of analysis, interpretations,
evaluation, critique and construction of argumentation in everyday
language”.
3 Their
main motivation was that formal logic is
rather hard to apply to everyday arguments. Everyday arguments – like
the student’s argument for deserving a better grade, the husband’s
argument for getting a new car – are never ex-plicitly formulated as
deductive arguments and trying to put them in deductive form requires
the addition of further premises. These additional premises, however,
often seem arbitrary in the sense that there is little justification
for supposing that the arguer would accept them. Indeed, these
additional premises would often be obviously false. So in-formal
logicians jettisoned the idea of deductive validity together with the
argument forms which may be assessed in terms of deductive validity.
The new understanding of argument structure and validity they developed
has made it possible to raise the question whether visual messages can
constitute arguments. The majority of theoreticians has answered this
question affirmatively.
4
The Idea of Visual Argument
From the perspective of formal logic
the idea of visual argument looks
odd to say the least: premises and conclusions ar sentences, but
pictures are not made up of sentences. But O’Keefe has suggested a
broader conception of argument which is more hospitable to visual
arguments. On his understanding arguments involve “a linguistically
explicable claim and one or more linguistically explicable
reasons”.
5 This
implies that arguments do not necessarily have to
be linguistic, they only have to be
linguistically
explicable. Visual
contents are certainly linguistically explicable, since we can describe
in words what pic-tures show. To put it differently, what matters for
arguments is propositional content, and propositions can also be
expressed by visual means. This conception of argument makes
theoretical room for visual arguments. Informal logicians then went on
to argue that some pictures described in the way we usually describe
pictures actually constitute arguments. Even though these arguments are
rarely complete in the sense of explicitly containing the claim and all
the reasons, verbal arguments are also often incomplete, for the simple
reason that what the recipient of the message knows or can easily
figure out does not have to be explicitly stated.
6
The Reconstruction of Visual Arguments
So the only important difference between visual and verbal arguments is
that the claim and reasons making up a verbal argument are linguistic,
whereas those making up visual arguments are at least partly merely
linguistically explicable. Verbal arguments thus consist of a
linguistically formulated claim, i.e. conclusion and one or more
linguistically formulated reasons, i.e. a single set or multiple sets
of premises, whereas in visual argu-ments at least some of the premises
or the conclusion is not expressed in linguistic form. In the case of a
simple argument relying on a single reason the picture is this (Table
1).
Verbal
argument |
Argument |
Visual
argument |
linguistic |
Premises
Conclusion
|
linguistically explicable |
Table 1
The question we have to address now
is how this difference shows up in
the reconstruction of visual arguments. What informal logicians mean by
reconstruction is a fully explicit and transparent statement of the
argument, which contains all elements necessary for its evaluation. So
reconstruction involves more than a lay understanding of the argument –
it is not a skill which everyone possesses but a learned art drawing on
technical concepts. The reconstruction of an argument consists of the
following elements:
- Identifying the conclusion.
- Identifying the premises.
- Rephrasing the sentences.
- Making implicit elements explicit.
- Building up the structure of the argument.
These should not be conceived as consecutive steps of reconstruction,
because reconstruction, which is a sophisticated process of
understanding, like all other processes of understanding, moves in a
hermeneutic circle. It is by identifying the conclusion that we may
select the parts of the text which function as premises and set them
apart from other parts, like explanations, incidental remarks, purely
rhetorical elements, etc. But it is only by identifying the premises
that we can understand exactly what conclusion the author of the text
is arguing for. These two elements are present even in the lay
under-standing of arguments. However, a reconstruction involves more.
First of all, the possible ambiguities of the text need to be resolved.
The terminology must be unified (e.g. in the student’s argument for a
better grade which involves both the terms “unfair” and “unjust” we may
have to substitute one for the other depending on how the argument
goes). It is changes like these which the term ‘rephrasing the
sentences’ signifies. In addition, the implicit elements must be made
explicit otherwise the relevance or failure of relevance of the premise
cannot be assessed. (E.g. the student’s showing his detailed notes of
the readings is relevant only because this demonstrates that he has
studied a lot – to which the teacher may respond that it is not the
amount of studying which is relevant for the grade but whether the
material has been learned.) When all the premises and the conclusion
have been layed out, it needs to be spelled out how they are connected,
how the premises are supposed to support the conclusion. (E.g. if the
student explains that he has studied a lot and he has only one point
missing for the passing grade, is he advancing two separate reasons for
his claim of deserving a better grade, or is he arguing that it is in
light of his hard work that the missing point should be ignored?)
When it comes to visual arguments, we cannot simply
identify the conclusion and the premises, since we do not have a
linguistic text in which we can isolate them. What we need instead is
their linguistic formulation. Continuing down the list, pictures and
films, being non-linguistic, are free of the occasional linguistic
ambiguities and inaccuracies, and this renders rephrasing sentences
superfluous; if there are not any sentences, there is nothing to
rephrase. The rest of the elements remain the same. Visual arguments
may contain implicit premises just as verbal arguments do. It is worth
drawing attention to the distinction between linguistic formulation and
addition of implicit elements. Linguistic formulation transforms the
visual argument into a verbal one, whereas making the implicit explicit
consists in providing what is missing. Linguistic formulation consists
in changing the modality of content, making the implicit explicit
amounts to enriching the content (Table 2).
|
Verbal
argument
|
|
Visual
argument |
1.
|
Identifying the conclusion.
|
1.
|
Linguistic formulation of conclusion. |
2.
|
Identifying the premises. |
2.
|
Linguistic formulation of premises. |
3.
|
Rephrasing the sentences. |
3.
|
---- |
4.
|
Making implicit elements
explicit. |
4.
|
Making implicit
elements explicit. |
5.
|
Building up the structure.
|
5.
|
Building up the structure.
|
Table 2
It seems, then, that the
reconstruction of visual argumentation follows
broadly the same method as the reconstruction of verbal arguments. It
is worth pointing out that there are arguments termed “multimodal”,
7 which feature both
verbal and visual elements. Indeed, commercials
making use of visual argumentation are typically multimodal, and the
Dove commercial to be analyzed is no exception.
Given this picture of the reconstruction of visual
arguments it is clear that the evaluation of visual arguments (e.g.
identifying unacceptable premises or fallacies) is also fairly similar
to that of verbal arguments. The reason is that reconstruction amounts
to a verbal representation of the argument, and the verbal
representation of an argument is a verbal argument, and as such, all
the usual methods of assessment of verbal arguments are appropriate.
Argument Schemes
Before offering a reconstruction of the Dove commercial we need to say
a few words about the apparatus to be deployed. Informal logicians have
suggested various conceptual devices to replace the apparatus of the
logical connectives geared to capturing deductive structure. The one we
will make use of, the apparatus of argumentation schemes, bears some
similarity to the logical forms of deductive logicians. A valid logical
form is an abstract structure made up of linguistic elements
characterized solely in terms of their identity or non-identity and
logical connectives such that if it is filled in with linguistic
elements in a way which renders the premises true, then the conclusion
is also necessarily rendered true. An argumentation scheme is also an
abstract structure which can be filled in with various linguistic
elements. But filling it in with linguistic elements which make the
premises true does not necessarily make the conclusion true. It makes
the conclusion only presumptively true, meaning that we may accept the
conclusion as true as long as we are not given a stronger reason
against the conclusion or a consideration that undermines the argument.
Argument schemes filled in with true premises thus supply only
defeasible justification for the conclusion. These argumentation
schemes are also constituted in parts by identical linguistic elements,
but instead of logical connectives they involve non-logical expressions
such as similarity, cause, sign. Here is a somewhat simplified example:
A is true in this situation.
A is a sign of B.
B is true in this situation.
Filling in “There is smoke over
there” for
A and “There is
fire over
there” for
B, we get a
cogent, even if not conclusive argument for
B.
The argument would be defeated if it turned out the smoke was generated
by a high-powered smoke machine. This basic idea has been spelt out
differently by different authors. Here we will be drawing on Walton,
Reed, and Macagno’s argumentation schemes.
8
The Case Study
In 2006 Unilever started to air a commercial for a New Dove Intensive
Cream.
9 The
commercial, intended to convince customers that the
Dove product is a better moisturizer than Nivea’s market leading
product, runs as follows.
A female hand touches first the Dove then the Nivea product, placed
left and right, respectively (Figure 1/1). Then we are presented with
two containers with the names of the two brands, in which the amount of
cream appears to be the same. After that, the camera focuses on the
containers (Figure 1/2–3–4). A dying tulip is placed first in the Dove
cream (Figure 1/5), then in the Nivea product (Figure 1/6). The flowers
are in bad shape, drooping in opposite directions; they obviously need
water. The camera shows them from the side, which makes their miserable
condition perfectly clear (Figure 1/7). At the 12th second of the
commercial the tulips are left alone to give them time to absorb the
creams (Figure 1/8). The changing light and the ticking of a clock
suggests that time passes. The camera focuses on the tulip of the Nivea
and we see that its condition does not visibly improve (Figure 1/9).
Figure 1
The camera zooms out and we see both tulips now. The passing of time is
shown on a virtual stopwatch (Figure 2/10). After ten hours, the tulip
left in the Dove product looks perfectly healthy, while Nivea’s tulip
is still somewhat drooping - a humiliating defeat (Figure 2/11). The
examiner chooses for the tulip treated with Dove (Figure 2/12). The
abandoned tulip is left in the Nivea moisturizer (Figure 2/13). The
tulip is retrieved from the left container and placed on the right
beside the moisturizer. The text reads “New Dove Intensive Cream” and
“Better moisturization, beautiful skin” (Figure 2/14–15). Notably, in
the Hungarian version of the advertisement the slogan was “Better
mois-turization and beautiful skin” (Figure 2).
Figure 2
The Reconstruction of Visual
Arguments in the “Tulip Test”
Following the procedure outlined earlier, in reconstructing a visual
argument we must start with the linguistic formulation of the
conclusion and the premises. The former presents no difficulties:
since this is a commercial for Dove, the conclusion should be something
like “You should use Dove”. What about the premises? One clue is
supplied by the text appearing at the end of the commercial, “Better
moisturization, beautiful skin”. Having superior moisturizing effect
and thus making the skin more beautiful is certainly a good reason for
choosing Dove.
Notice, however, that it is at the very end of the commercial that this
text appears, which suggests that it might be a conclusion deriving
from what we saw before. So what did we see? We saw that Dove improves
the condition of the drooping tulip much better than Nivea does. As we
all know, flowers need water, so it is by supplying water, i.e. by
moisturizing that Dove improves the condition of the tulip. So one
premise leading to the conclusion presented in text (which, in turn, is
a premise for the final conclusion that we should use Dove) is
something like this: “Dove moisturizes the tulip better than Nivea
does”.
The next question is how we move from this premise to the conclusion
than Dove moisturizes the skin better. It is at this point that the
idea of argumentation schemes can be invoked, as structures linking
premises to conclusions. Since the commercial derives a conclusion
about the skin from a premise about the tulip, it presumably relies on
the idea that the two are similar. This suggests that it is an argument
from analogy. This argumentation scheme is characterized by Walton,
Reed, and Macagno as follows:
Argument from analogy:
- Generally, case C1 is
similar to case C2.
- In case C1, A is true.
- A is true in case C2.10
In the present case C1 is the case of
the tulip, C2 is the case of the
skin, thus the analogical argument offered in the commercial is this:
Argument from analogy in this case:
- The skin is similar to the tulip.
- Dove moisturizes the tulip
much better than Nivea does.
- Dove moisturizes the skin better than Nivea does.
Notice that in identifying the two
premises we perform different
reconstructive operations. In the case of the second premise we merely
put what we saw in the commercial in verbal form, which we called
linguistic formulation. But the pictures do not show anything like the
first premise. We find out about it by asking how the first premise
might lead to the conclusion, and its specific form is identified with
the help of an argumentation scheme. So what we do here is performing
the reconstructive operation of making the implicit explicit.
We have already noted that the final conclusion of the commercial is
that we should use Dove and that it is inferred from the premise that
Dove moisturizes better and makes the skin more beautiful. But how
exactly does the inference go? Moisturizers are supposed to make our
skin more beautiful, which we think is a good thing. This suggests that
the inference utilizes the argument scheme from positive consequences.
This scheme is described by Walton, Reed, and Macagno in this way:
Argument from Positive Consequences:
- If A is brought about,
then good consequences will plausibly occur.
- Therefore, A should be brought about.11
Variable A is in this case using
Dove, and the good conseqences in
question consist in having better moisturized and hence more beautiful
skin. So the argument runs as fol¬lows:
Argument from Positive Consequences in this case:
- If you use Dove, then
it is plausible that your skin will be better
moisturized and be more beautiful.
- Therefore, you should use Dove.
What remains is the final
reconstructive operation, building up the
structure of the argument. The argument from positive consequences
takes us to the final conclusion of the commercial, and the role of the
argument from analogy is to support the premise of the argument.
However, the conclusion of the argument from analogy is not exactly the
same as the premise of the argument from positive consequences, since
the latter mentions beautiful skin (italicized above), which the
former does not. This gap is filled by the textual element of the
commercial, “Better moisturization, beautiful skin”, which can be
construed in this context as saying that better moisturized skin is
more beautiful. Construing it in this way involves the reconstructive
operation characteristic only of verbal arguments, rephrasing the
sentences.
So the argument can be put together
as follows (Table 3):
1.
|
The skin is similar to the
tulip.
|
implicit premise |
2.
|
Dove moisturizes the tulip much better
than Nivea
does. |
explicit visual premise |
3.
|
Dove moisturizes the skin better than
Nivea
does. |
from 1. and 2. by argumentation from
analogy |
4.
|
Better moisturized skin is more
beautiful.
|
textual premise rephrased |
5.
|
If you use Dove, then it is plausible
that your
skin will be better moisturized and be more
beautiful.
|
from 3. and 4. |
6.
|
Therefore, you should use Dove.
|
from 5. by argument from positive consequences |
Table 3
Summary
We have argued first that the
reconstruction of visual arguments
follows by and large the same procedure as that of verbal ones. We have
found only two differences. In place of the identification of premises
and conclusions in verbal arguments we have the linguistic formulation
of premises and conclusion. Also, in the case of visual arguments there
is nothing corresponding to the reconstructive operation of rephrasing
the premises. What is especially interesting and might even be
surprising is the similarity that the operation of making the implicit
explicit is also part of the reconstruction of visual arguments.
To see how the reconstruction works in practice we have provided a
detailed re-construction of a commercial, pointing out how the
theoretically motivated reconstructive transformations actually show up
in practice. The reconstruction also allows to draw a more specific
conclusion, namely that the apparatus of argumentation schemes can be
applied to the reconstruction of visual arguments as well.
[1] Supported by the
ÚNKP-16-3 New National
Excellence Program of the Ministry of the Human Capacity. We would like
to thank István Danka, János Tanács, and Réka Markovich
for their invaluable contribution to the research. We would also like
to thank the Hungarian Scientific Research Fund (OTKA) for the
financial support provided by grant K 109456.
[2] The Hungarian
Competion Authority initiated a proceeding against this
advertisement and found it deceitful.
[3] F. H. van
Eemeren
et al., Handbook of Argumentation Theory, Amsterdam:
John Benjamins, 2014, pp. 373–374. Eemeren is here referring to R. H.
Johnson and J. A. Blair, “The Current State of Informal Logic”,
Informal Logic 9 (1987), pp. 147–51.
[4] Birdsell’s,
Groarke’s and Blair’s papers in the 1996 special issue of
Argumentation and Advocacy are especially important.
[5] Anthony
Blair,
“The Possibility and Actuality of Visual Arguments”,
Argumentation and Advocacy, vol. 33, no. 1 (1996), p. 24.
[6] Opponents of
the
existence of visual arguments often claim that
pictures are unsuitable for the expression of arguments because they
are intrinsically ambiguous (David Fleming, “Can there be Visual
Arguments?”, Argumentation & Advocacy, vol. 33, no. 1 [1996], p.
11). That is a serious concern which cannot be easily dismissed;
nevertheless, we agree with Blair (op. cit., p. 24) that the difference
between the verbal and the visual in this respect is merely a
difference in degree. We trust that the reconstruction of the
commercial below at least illustrates that this concern is unfounded.
[7] J. Anthony Blair,
“Probative Norms for Multimodal Visual Arguments”, Argumentation, vol.
29, no. 2 (2015), pp. 217–233.
[8] D. N. Walton et
al., Argumentation Schemes, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2008.
[9] Unilever Germany
–
tulip test:
http://www.tvspots.tv/video/42773/unilever-germany-tulip-test.
[10] D. N. Walton et
al., op. cit., p. 315.
[11] Ibid., p. 332.